Wednesday, March 02, 2005

Consumed by the Spirit of Irreverence as I am

I'd like to point out that my religion has three bibles. There's The Bible, which, if you believe in it, is destined to get top billing. Next comes Atlas Shrugged, followed by Human Action.

God, Ayn Rand and Ludwig von Mises.

Not an obvious troika. Rand and Mises, sure, but they were both atheists and Rand was quite militant about it. I'm making no friends at CapMag or ARI by admitting that I place the Bible above her. I'm sure that even the kids at The Objectivist Center are turning their backs on me as you read this.

I say, "Relax! If you're right, this BS will wither away in good time." I don't think religion can be defeated in head to head debate. If it's wrong, history will bypass it. But, as Omni said, my experience says there's something there. My prayers often seem to work.

And don't forget how much I enjoy The Wisdom of China and India, by Lin Yutang.

I've talked plenty about the first two recently. I don't think I've ever posted an extended quote from Human Action.

I have The Scholars' Edition. Page 14:
On Happiness

In colloquial speech we call a man "happy" who has succeeded in attaining his ends. A more adequate description of his state would be that he is happier than he was before. There is however no valid objection to a usage that defines human action as the striving for happiness.

But we must avoid current misunderstandings. The ultimate goal of human action is always the satisfaction of the acting man's desire. There is no standard of greater or lesser satisfaction other than individual judgments of value, different for various people and for the same people at various times. What makes a man feel uneasy and less uneasy is established by him from the standard of his own will and judgment, from his personal and subjective valuation. Nobody is in a position to decree what should make a fellow man happier.

To establish this fact does not refer in any way to the antitheses of egoism and altruism, of materialism and idealism, of individualism and collectivism, of atheism and religion. There are people whose only aim is to improve the condition of their own ego. There are other people with whom awareness of the troubles of their fellow men causes as much uneasiness as or even more uneasiness than their own wants. There are people who desire nothing else than the satisfaction of their appetites for sexual intercourse, food, drinks, fine homes, and other material things. But other men care more for the satisfactions commonly called "higher" and "ideal." There are individuals eager to adjust their actions to the requirements of social cooperation; there are; on the other hand, refractory people who defy the rules of social life. There are people for whom the ultimate goal of the earthly pilgrimage is the preparation for a life of bliss. There are other people who do not believe in the teachings of any religion and do not allow their actions to be influenced by them.

Praxeology is indifferent to the ultimate goals of action. Its findings are valid for all kinds of action irrespective of the ends aimed at. It is a science of means, not of ends. It applies the term happiness in a purely formal sense. In the praxeological terminology the proposition: man's unique aim is to attain happiness, is tautological. It does not imply any statement about the state of affairs from which man expects happiness.

The idea that the incentive of human activity is always some uneasiness and its aim always to remove such uneasiness as far as possible, that is to make the acting men feel happier, is the essence of the teachings of Eudaemonism and Hedonism. Epicurean [Greek - aparaeia] is that state of perfect happiness and contentment at which all human activity aims without ever wholly attaining it. In the face of the grandeur of this cognition it is of little avail only that many representatives of this philosophy failed to recognize the purely formal character of the notions pain and pleasure and gave them a material and carnal meaning. The theological, mystical, and other schools of a heteronomous ethic did not shake the core of Epicureanism because they could not raise any other objection than its neglect of the "higher" and "nobler" pleasures. It is true that the writings of many earlier champions of Eudaemonism, Hedonism, and Utilitarianism are in some points open to misinterpretation. But the language of modern philosophers and still more that of the modern economists is so precise and straightforward that no misinterpretation can possibly occur.

Perhaps I don't normally make it clear that all my posts are open for debate.

This is a further development of Utilitarianism. There are some I know who should be aware that Henry Hazlitt expanded on this line of thought in The Foundations of Morality. (And see this link for a better review that I could have written.)